According to the logicality of language hypothesis (hereinafter, LLH), logical considerations are relevant for syntactic formation to the point that they are needed to explain some ungrammaticalities (Gajewski 2002, 2009; Fox & Hackl 2006; Chierchia 2013, 2021; Abrusán 2014; Del Pinal 2019, 2021). In other words, the syntactic unacceptability of some linguistic constructions is traced back to their logical status, suggesting that speakers judge a word-sequence as ungrammatical or ill-formed when it is always false or always true. The aim of this work is to examine the recent literature that attempts to offer alternative explanations and test the solidity of the objections it proposes. In particular, we will look at cases concerning identity and co-binding.
Chief evidence in support of LLH comes from word-sequences, such as (1)–(4), judged ungrammatical qua contradictory.
(1) *Some students but John passed the exam
(2) *There are any cookies left
(3) *How fast didn’t you drive?
(4) *How did John regret that he behaved at the party?
Other word-sequences, such as (5)–(7), are judged ungrammatical qua tautological.
(5) *There is every fly in my soup
(6) *Mary is taller than no student is
(7) *At least zero students smoked
However, in general, contradictions and tautologies are not ungrammatical.
(8) This table is red and it is not red
(9) It is raining or it is not raining
Within LLH, the syntactic acceptability of (8)–(9) is not questioned. As a result, the asymmetry between the ungrammaticality of (1)–(7), due to their logical status, and the grammaticality of (8)–(9), notwithstanding their logical status, has to be accounted for. This is the so-called «analyticity puzzle».
According to an early articulation of LLH (Gajewski 2002, 2009; Fox & Hackl 2006; Chierchia 2013), one must assume a purely linguistic logic and associate linguistic constructions with particularly austere representations, which reveal truly contradictory or tautological contents only in the case of constructions later judged ungrammatical. According to an alternative articulation, on the other hand, contradictions and tautologies are ungrammatical insofar as it is not possible to make them informative, by modulating their lexical content (Del Pinal 2019, 2021; Pistoia-Reda & Sauerland 2021; Pistoia-Reda & San Mauro 2021).
There have been attempts to explain the rejection of (1)–(7) typologically, i.e., in terms of a failure of composition (Abrusán, Asher & Van de Cruys 2021). To that extent, (1)–(7) would be similar to examples of semantic anomaly, such as (10)–(11).
(10) #Tigers are Zermelo-Fraenkel sets
(11) #My toothbrush is pregnant
According to LLH, (1)–(7) are only superficially uninterpretable: when analysed, they receive an interpretation, which is that of being either contradictory or tautological. According to Abrusán, Asher & Van de Cruys (2021), (1)–(7) are instead uninterpretable for, in building up their semantic representation, an insuperable semantic problem is encountered.
The critical objective of Abrusán, Asher & Van de Cruys (2021) is primarily the early articulation proposed by Gajewski (2002, 2009). However, according to them, the alternative articulation proposed by Del Pinal (2019, 2021) also faces problems. In particular, it could not explain the syntactic acceptability of (12) where, they say, we insist on making the two predicates in (8) be identical, hence leaving no space for meaning modulation.
(12) This table is red1 and not red2 and the property red1 is identical to the property red2
However, sentences concerning identity are not always interpreted as strict identities. In other words, they do not always entail that the pre-copular and the post-copular DPs are co-extensional (Fiorin & Delfitto 2024). Indeed, in a pragmatically supportive context, even possessive binding becomes acceptable:
(13) Annei is identical to heri mother
In (13) we do not take Anne and her mother to be co-extensional, but to share certain typical characteristics (e.g.: they behave in the exact same way, or they have a striking physical resemblance). We will argue that, similarly, (12) does not necessarily entail that red1 and red2 are co-extensional, therefore pragmatic considerations can still make the word-sequence non-contradictory.
Furthermore, we will argue that moving from logical identity to logical identification is the key to account for other examples, involving co-binding, considered problematic for language logicality, such as (14) and (15).
(14) Johni is smarter than himselfi
(15) Johni is himselfi
To conclude, non-typological explanations of (1)–(7) have not yet been decisively ruled out, and the typological explanation offered by Abrusán, Asher & Van de Cruys (2021) does not represent a defeat for language logicality but a redefinition of it: given that the peculiarity of (1)–(7) is due to types denoting a context-invariant logical meaning, logical considerations are relevant for syntactic formation after all.
References
Abrusán M., 2014, Weak Island Semantics, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Abrusán M., N. Asher & T. Van de Cruys, 2021, «Grammaticality and Meaning Shift» in G. Sagi, J. Woods (eds.), The Semantic Conception of Logic, Cambridge (MA), Cambridge University Press, pp. 249–276.
Chierchia G., 2013, Logic in Grammar: Polarity, Free Choice, and Intervention, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Chierchia G., 2021, «On Being Trivial: Grammar vs. Logic» in G. Sagi, J. Woods (eds.), The Semantic Conception of Logic, Cambridge (MA), Cambridge University Press, pp. 227–248.
Del Pinal G., 2019, «The Logicality of Language: A New Take on Triviality, “Ungrammaticality”, and Logical Form», Noûs, 53, 4, pp. 785–818.
Del Pinal G., 2021, «The Logicality of Language: Contextualism vs. Semantic Minimalism», Manuscript, University of Illinois.
Fiorin G. & D. Delfitto, 2024, «Binding in copular sentences and the logic of identification», Presentation delivered at IGG49.
Fox D. & M. Hackl, 2006, «The Universal Density of Measurement», Linguistics and Philosophy, 29, 5, pp. 537–586.
Gajewski J., 2002, «L-analyticity and Natural Language», Manuscript, MIT.
Gajewski J., 2009, «L-triviality and Grammar», Handout, UConn Logic Group.
Pistoia-Reda S. & L. San Mauro, 2021, «On Logicality and Natural Logic», Natural Language Semantics, 29, 3, pp. 501–506.
Pistoia-Reda S. & U. Sauerland, 2021, «Analyticity and Modulation: Broadening the Rescale Perspective on Language Logicality», International Review of Pragmatics, 13, 1, pp. 1–13.